Sextus Empiricus and Greek scepticism by Mary Mills Patrick - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

[1] Saisset _Op. cit._ p. 237.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 178.

[3] Zeller III. 38; Ritter IV. 277.

[4] Saisset _Op. cit._ p. 231.

The two Tropes are founded on the principle that anything must

be known through itself or through something else. It cannot be

known through itself, because of the discord existing between

all things of the senses and intellect, nor can it be known

through something else, as then either the _regressus in infinitum_ or the _circulus in probando_ follow.[1]

Diogenes

Laertius does not refer to these two Tropes.

In regard to all these Tropes of the suspension of judgment,

Sextus has well remarked in his introduction to them, that they

are included in the eighth, or that of relation.[2]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 178-179.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 39.

_The Tropes of Aetiology_. The eight Tropes against causality

belong chronologically before the five Tropes of Agrippa, in the

history of the development of sceptical thought. They have a

much closer connection with the spirit of Scepticism than the

Tropes of Agrippa, including, as they do, the fundamental

thought of Pyrrhonism, _i.e._, that the phenomena do not reveal

the unknown.

The Sceptics did not deny the phenomena, but they denied that

the phenomena are signs capable of being interpreted, or of

revealing the reality of causes. It is impossible by a research

of the signs to find out the unknown, or the explanation of

things, as the Stoics and Epicureans claim. The theory of

Aenesidemus which lies at the foundation of his eight Tropes

against aetiology, is given to us by Photius as follows:[1]

"There are no visible signs of the unknown, and those who

believe in its existence are the victims of a vain illusion."

This statement of Aenesidemus is confirmed by a fuller explanation of it given later on by Sextus.[2] If phenomena are

not signs of the unknown there is no causality, and a refutation

of causality is a proof of the impossibility of science, as all

science is the science of causes, the power of studying causes

from effects, or as Sextus calls them, phenomena.

It is very noticeable to any one who reads the refutation of

causality by Aenesidemus, as given by Sextus,[3] that there is

no reference to the strongest argument of modern Scepticism,

since the time of Hume, against causality, namely that the

origin of the idea of causality cannot be so accounted for as to

justify our relying upon it as a form of cognition.[4]

[1] _Myriob._ 170 B. 12.

[2] _Adv. Math._ VIII. 207.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 180-186.

[4] Ueberweg _Op. cit._ p. 217.

The eight Tropes are directed against the possibility of knowledge of nature, which Aenesidemus contested against in all

his Tropes, the ten as well as the eight.[1] They are written

from a materialistic standpoint. These Tropes are given with

illustrations by Fabricius as follows: I. Since aetiology in general refers to things that are unseen,

it does not give testimony that is incontestable in regard to

phenomena. For example, the Pythagoreans explain the distance of

the planets by a musical proportion.

II. From many equally plausible reasons which might be given for

the same thing, one only is arbitrarily chosen, as some explain

the inundation of the Nile by a fall of snow at its source,

while there could be other causes, as rain, or wind, or the

action of the sun.

III. Things take place in an orderly manner, but the causes

presented do not show any order, as for example, the motion of

the stars is explained by their mutual pressure, which does not

take into account the order that reigns among them.

IV. The unseen things are supposed to take place in the same way

as phenomena, as vision is explained in the same way as the

appearance of images in a dark room.

V. Most philosophers present theories of aetiology which agree

with their own individual hypotheses about the elements, but not

with common and accepted ideas, as to explain the world by atoms

like Epicurus, by homoeomeriae like Anaxagoras, or by matter and

form like Aristotle.

VI. Theories are accepted which agree with individual hypotheses, and others equally probable are passed by, as

Aristotle's explanation of comets, that they are a collection of

vapors near the earth, because that coincided with his theory of

the universe.

VII. Theories of aetiology are presented which conflict not only

with individual hypotheses, but also with phenomena, as to admit

like Epicurus an inclination or desire of the soul, which was

incompatible with the necessity which he advocated.

VIII. The inscrutable is explained by things equally inscrutable, as the rising of sap in plants is explained by the

attraction of a sponge for water, a fact contested by some.[2]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 98.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 180-186; Fabricius, Cap. XVII. 180 z.

Diogenes does not mention these Tropes in this form, but he

gives a _resumé_ of the general arguments of the Sceptics

against aetiology,[1] which has less in common with the eight

Tropes of Aenesidemus, than with the presentation of the subject

by Sextus later,[2] when he multiplies his proofs exceedingly to

show [Greek: mêden einai aition]. Although the Tropes of Aenesidemus have a dialectic rather than an objective character,

it would not seem that he made the distinction, which is so

prominent with Sextus, between the signs [Greek: hypomnêstika]

and [Greek: endeiktika],[3] especially as Diogenes sums up his

argument on the subject with the general assertion,

[Greek:

Sêmeion ouk einai],[4] and proceeds to introduce the logical

consequence of the denial of aetiology. The summing up of the

Tropes of Aenesidemus is given as follows, in the _Hypotyposes_,

by Sextus:--"A cause in harmony with all the sects of philosophy, and with Scepticism, and with phenomena, is perhaps

not possible, for the phenomena and the unknown altogether

disagree."[5]

It is interesting to remark in connection with the seventh of

these Tropes, that Aenesidemus asserts that causality has only a

subjective value, which from his materialistic standpoint was an

argument against its real existence, and the same argument is

used by Kant to prove that causality is a necessary condition of

thought.[6]

Chaignet characterises the Tropes of Aenesidemus as false and

sophistical,[7] but as Maccoll has well said, they are remarkable for their judicious and strong criticism, and are

directed against the false method of observing facts through the

light of preconceived opinion.[8] They have, however, a stronger

critical side than sceptical, and show the positive tendency of

the thought of Aenesidemus.

[1] Diog. IX. 11, 96-98.

[2] _Hyp._ III. 24-28.

[3] _Adv. Math._ VIII. 151.

[4] Diog. IX. 11, 96.

[5] _Hyp._ I. 185.

[6] Compare Maccoll _Op. cit._ p. 77.

[7] Chaignet _Op. cit._ 507.

[8] Maccoll _Op. cit._ p. 88.

CHAPTER IV.

_Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus._

A paragraph in the First Book of the _Hypotyposes_ which has

given rise to much speculation and many different theories, is

the comparison which Sextus makes of Scepticism with the philosophy of Heraclitus.[1] In this paragraph the statement is

made that Aenesidemus and his followers, [Greek: hoi peri ton

Ainêsidêmon], said that Scepticism is the path to the philosophy

of Heraclitus, because the doctrine that contradictory predicates appear to be applicable to the same thing, leads the

way to the one that contradictory predicates are in reality

applicable to the same thing.[2] [Greek: hoi peri ton Ainêsidêmon elegon hodon einai tên skeptikên agôgên epi tên

Hêrakleiteion philosophian, dioti proêgeitai tou tanantia peri

to auto hyparchein to tanantia peri to auto phainesthai]. As the

Sceptics say that contradictory predicates appear to be applicable to the same thing, the Heraclitans come from this to

the more positive doctrine that they are in reality so.[3]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 210.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 210.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 210.

This connection which Aenesidemus is said to have affirmed

between Scepticism and the philosophy of Heraclitus is earnestly

combated by Sextus, who declares that the fact that contradictory predicates appear to be applicable to the same

thing is not a dogma of the Sceptics, but a fact which presents

itself to all men, and not to the Sceptics only. No one for

instance, whether he be a Sceptic or not, would dare to say that

honey does not taste sweet to those in health, and bitter to

those who have the jaundice, so that Heraclitus begins from a

preconception common to all men, as to us also, and perhaps to

the other schools of philosophy as well.[1] As the statement

concerning the appearance of contradictory predicates in regard

to the same thing is not an exclusively sceptical one, then

Scepticism is no more a path to the philosophy of Heraclitus

than to other schools of philosophy, or to life, as all use

common subject matter. "But we are afraid that the Sceptical

School not only does not help towards the knowledge of the

philosophy of Heraclitus, but even hinders that result.

Since

the Sceptic accuses Heraclitus of having rashly dogmatised,

presenting on the one hand the doctrine of

'conflagration' and

on the other that 'contradictory predicates are in reality

applicable to the same thing.'"[2] "It is absurd, then, to say

that this conflicting school is a path to the sect with which it

conflicts. It is therefore absurd to say that the Sceptical

School is a path to the philosophy of Heraclitus."[3]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 211.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 212.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 212.

This is not the only place in the writings of Sextus which

states that Aenesidemus at some time of his life was an advocate

of the doctrines of Heraclitus. In no instance, however, where

Sextus refers to this remarkable fact, does he offer any explanation of it, or express any bitterness against Aenesidemus, whom he always speaks of with respect as a leader

of the Sceptical School. We are thus furnished with one of the

most difficult problems of ancient Scepticism, the problem of

reconciling the apparent advocacy of Aenesidemus of the teachings of Heraclitus with his position in the Sceptical

School.

A comparison with each other of the references made by Sextus

and other writers to the teachings of Aenesidemus, and a consideration of the result, gives us two pictures of Aenesidemus which conflict most decidedly with each other. We

have on the one hand, the man who was the first to give Pyrrhonism a position as an influential school, and the first to

collect and present to the world the results of preceding

Sceptical thought. He was the compiler of the ten Tropes of

[Greek: epochê], and perhaps in part their author, and the

author of the eight Tropes against aetiology.[1] He develops his

Scepticism from the standpoint that neither the senses nor the

intellect can give us any certain knowledge of reality.[2] He

denied the possibility of studying phenomena as signs of the

unknown.[3] He denied all possibility of truth, and the reality

of motion, origin and decay. There was according to his teaching

no pleasure or happiness, and no wisdom or supreme good.

He

denied the possibility of finding out the nature of things, or

of proving the existence of the gods, and finally he declared

that no ethical aim is possible.

[1] _Hyp._ I. 180.

[2] Photius 170, B. 12.

[3] _Adv. Math._ VIII. 40.

The picture on the other hand, presented to us by Sextus and

Tertullian, is that of a man with a system of beliefs and

dogmas, which lead, he says, to the philosophy of Heraclitus. In

strange contradiction to his assertion of the impossibility of

all knowledge, he advocates a theory that the original substance

is air,[1] which is most certainly a dogma, although indeed a

deviation from the teachings of Heraclitus, of which Sextus

seemed unconscious, as he says, [Greek: to te on kata ton

Hêrakleiton aêr estin, hôs physin ho Ainêsidêmos].

Aenesidemus

dogmatised also regarding number and time and unity of the

original world-stuff.[2] He seems to have dogmatised further

about motion,[3] and about the soul.[4]

If Sextus' language is taken according to its apparent meaning,

we find ourselves here in the presence of a system of beliefs

which would be naturally held by a follower of the Stoic-Heraclitan physics,[5] and absolutely inexplicable from

the standpoint of a man who advocated so radical a Scepticism as

Aenesidemus. Sextus in the passage that we first quoted,[6]

expresses great indignation against the idea that Scepticism

could form the path to the philosophy of Heraclitus, but he does

not express surprise or indignation against Aenesidemus personally, or offer any explanation of the apparent contradiction; and while his writings abound in references to

him as a respected leader of the Sceptical School, he sometimes

seems to include him with the Dogmatics, mentioning him with the

[Greek: dogmatikôn philosophôn].[7] In fact, the task of presenting any consistent history of the development of thought

through which Aenesidemus passed is such a puzzling one, that

Brochard brilliantly remarks that possibly the best attitude to

take towards it would be to follow the advice of Aenesidemus

himself, and suspend one's judgment altogether regarding it. Is

it possible to suppose that so sharp and subtle a thinker as

Aenesidemus held at the same time such opposing opinions?

[1] _Adv. Math._ X. 233.

[2] _Adv. Math._ IX. 337; X. 216.

[3] _Adv. Math._ X. 38.

[4] _Adv. Math._ VII. 349.

[5] Compare Zeller _Op. cit._ III. p. 33.

[6] _Hyp._ I. 210-212.

[7] _Adv. Math._ VIII. 8; X. 215.

The conjecture that he was first a Heraclitan Stoic, and later a

Sceptic, which might be possible, does not offer any explanation

of Sextus' statement, that he regarded Scepticism as a path to

the philosophy of Heraclitus. Nor would it be logical to think

that after establishing the Sceptical School in renewed influence and power, he reverted to the Heraclitan theories as

they were modified by the Stoics. These same theories were the

cause of his separation from the Academy, for his chief accusation against the Academy was that it was adopting the

dogmatism of the Stoics.[1] The matter is complicated by the

fact that Tertullian also attributes to Aenesidemus anthropological and physical teachings that agree with the

Stoical Heraclitan doctrines. It is not strange that in view of

these contradictory assertions in regard to the same man, some

have suggested the possibility that they referred to two different men of the same name, a supposition, however, that no

one has been able to authoritatively vindicate.

Let us consider briefly some of the explanations which have been

attempted of the apparent heresy of Aenesidemus towards the

Sceptical School. We will begin with the most ingenious, that of

Pappenheim.[2]

Pappenheim claims that Sextus was not referring to Aenesidemus

himself in these statements which he joins with his name. In the

most important of these, the one quoted from the _Hypotyposes_,[3] which represents Aenesidemus as claiming that

Scepticism is the path to the philosophy of Heraclitus, the

expression used is [Greek: hoi peri ton Ainêsidêmon], and in

many of the other places where Sextus refers to the dogmatic

statements of Aenesidemus, the expression is either

[Greek: hoi

peri ton Ainêsidêmon], or [Greek: Ainêsidêmos kath'

Hêrakleiton], while when Sextus quotes Aenesidemus to sustain

Scepticism, he uses his name alone.

[1] Compare Zeller _Op. cit._ III. p. 16.

[2] _Die angebliche Heraclitismus des Skeptikers Ainesidemos_, Berlin 1889.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 210-212.

Pappenheim thinks that Sextus' conflict was not with the dead

Aenesidemus, who had lived two centuries before him, but with

his own contemporaries. He also seeks to prove that Sextus could

not have gained his knowledge of these sayings of Aenesidemus

from any of Aenesidemus' own writings, as neither by the ancients, nor by later writers, was any book spoken of which

could well have contained them. Neither Aristocles nor Diogenes

mentions any such book.

Pappenheim also makes much of the argument that Sextus in no

instance seems conscious of inconsistency on the part of Aenesidemus, even when most earnestly combating his alleged

teachings, but in referring to him personally he always speaks

of him with great respect.

Pappenheim suggests, accordingly, that the polemic of Sextus was

against contemporaries, those who accepted the philosophy of

Heraclitus in consequence of, or in some connection with, the

teachings of Aenesidemus. He entirely ignores the fact that

there is no trace of any such school or sect in history, calling

themselves followers of "Aenesidemus according to Heraclitus,"

but still thinks it possible that such a movement existed in

Alexandria at the time of Sextus, where so many different sects

were found. Sextus use Aenesidemus' name in four different

ways:--alone, [Greek: hoi peri ton Ainesidêmon], [Greek: Ainêsidêmos kath' Hêrakleiton], and in one instance

[Greek: hoi

peri ton Ainêsidêmon kath' Hêrakleiton].[1]

[1] _Adv. Math._ VIII. 8.

Pappenheim advances the theory that some of these contemporaries

against whom Sextus directed his arguments had written a book

entitled [Greek: Ainêsidêmos kath' Hêrakleiton], to prove the

harmony between Aenesidemus and Heraclitus, and that it was from

this book that Sextus quoted the dogmatic statements which he

introduced with that formula. He claims, further, that the

passage quoted from _Hypotyposes I._ even, is directed against contemporaries, who founded their system of proofs of

the harmony between Aenesidemus and Heraclitus on the connection

of the celebrated formula which was such a favourite with the

Sceptics: "Contrary predicates appear to apply to the same

thing," with the apparent deduction from this, that

"Contrary

predicates in reality apply to the same thing." Sextus wishes,

according to Pappenheim, to prove to these contemporaries that

they had misunderstood Aenesidemus, and Sextus does not report

Aenesidemus to be a Dogmatic, nor to have taught the doctrines

of Heraclitus; neither has he misunderstood Aenesidemus, nor

consequently misrepresented him; but on the contrary, these

dogmatic quotations have nothing to do with Aenesidemus, but

refer altogether to contemporaries who pretended to be Sceptics

while they accepted the teachings of Heraclitus. Sextus naturally warmly combats this tendency, as he wishes to preserve

Pyrrhonism pure.

Brochard advocates a change of opinion on the part of Aenesidemus as an explanation of the difficulty in question.[1]

He starts from the supposition, the reasonableness of which we

shall consider later, that Aenesidemus had passed through one

change of opinion already when he severed his connection with

the New Academy; and to the two phases of his life, which such a

change has already made us familiar with, he adds a third.

Aenesidemus would not be the first who has accepted different

beliefs at different periods of his life, and Brochard claims

that such a development in the opinions of Aenesidemus is

logical. He does not accuse Aenesidemus of having, as might seem

from the perusal of Sextus, suddenly changed his basis, but

rather of having gradually come to accept much in the teachings

of Heraclitus. Aenesidemus modifies his Scepticism only to the

extent of pretending to know something of absolute reality. The

Sceptic says, "Contradictory predicates are apparently applicable to the same thing," and Aenesidemus accepts the

Heraclitan result--"Contradictory predicates are in reality

applicable to the same thing." From Sextus' report, Aenesidemus

would seem to have renounced his position as a Sceptic in saying

that Scepticism is the path to the philosophy of Heraclitus. He

does not, however, renounce Scepticism, but he finds it incomplete. In deliberating concerning the appearance of contradictory predicates in regard to the same object, he would

naturally ask, "Whence come these contradictory appearances?"

After having doubted all things, he wished to know wherefore he

doubts. The system of Heraclitus offers a solution, and he

accepts it. Contradictory predicates produce equilibrium in the

soul because they are an expression of reality.

[1] Brochard _Op. cit._ 272.

As a Sceptic he claims that knowledge is impossible, and he does

not find that the statement of Heraclitus disproves this, but

rather that it supports his theory. He had denied the existence

of science. He still does so, but now he knows why he denies it.

Brochard asks why it is any more impossible that Aenesidemus

should have been a follower of Heraclitus than that Protagoras

was so, as Protagoras was after all a Sceptic. In conclusion,

Brochard claims that the dogmatic theories attributed to Aenesidemus relate to the doctrine of the truth of contradictory

predicates, which seemed to him a logical explanation of the

foundation theories of Scepticism. It is right to call him a

Sceptic, for he was so, and that sincerely; and he deserves his

rank as one of the chiefs of the Sceptical School.

Coming now to the opinion of Zeller,[1] we find that he advocates a misconception of Aenesidemus on the part of Sextus.

The whole difficulty is removed, Zeller thinks, by the simple

fact that Sextus had not understood Aenesidemus; and as Tertullian and Sextus agree in this misconception of the views

of Aenesidemus, they must have been misled by consulting a

common author in regard to Aenesidemus, who confused what

Aenesidemus said of Heraclitus with his own opinion.

Zeller

maintains that the expression so often repeated by Sextus--[Greek: Ainêsidêmos kath' Hêrakleiton]--shows that some

one of Aenesidemus' books contained a report of Heraclitus'

doctrines, as Aenesidemus was in the habit of quoting as many

authorities as possible to sustain his Scepticism. To justify

his quotations fr