Mysticism and logic by Bertrand Russel. - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

_Chapter_

_Page_

I. _Mysticism and Logic_

1

II. _The Place of Science in a Liberal Education_

33

III. _A Free Man's Worship_

46

IV. _The Study of Mathematics_

58

V. _Mathematics and the Metaphysicians_

74

VI. _On Scientific Method in Philosophy_

97

VII. _The Ultimate Constituents of Matter_

125

VIII. _The Relation of Sense-data to Physics_

145

IX. _On the Notion of Cause_

180

X. _Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description_

209

MYSTICISM AND LOGIC AND OTHER ESSAYS

I

MYSTICISM AND LOGIC

Metaphysics, or the attempt to conceive the world as a whole by means

of thought, has been developed, from the first, by the union and

conflict of two very different human impulses, the one urging men

towards mysticism, the other urging them towards science. Some men

have achieved greatness through one of these impulses alone, others

through the other alone: in Hume, for example, the scientific impulse

reigns quite unchecked, while in Blake a strong hostility to science

co-exists with profound mystic insight. But the greatest men who have

been philosophers have felt the need both of science and of mysticism:

the attempt to harmonise the two was what made their life, and what

always must, for all its arduous uncertainty, make philosophy, to some

minds, a greater thing than either science or religion.

Before attempting an explicit characterisation of the scientific and

the mystical impulses, I will illustrate them by examples from two

philosophers whose greatness lies in the very intimate blending which

they achieved. The two philosophers I mean are Heraclitus and Plato.

Heraclitus, as every one knows, was a believer in universal flux: time

builds and destroys all things. From the few fragments that remain, it

is not easy to discover how he arrived at his opinions, but there are

some sayings that strongly suggest scientific observation as the

source.

"The things that can be seen, heard, and learned," he says, "are what

I prize the most." This is the language of the empiricist, to whom

observation is the sole guarantee of truth. "The sun is new every

day," is another fragment; and this opinion, in spite of its

paradoxical character, is obviously inspired by scientific reflection,

and no doubt seemed to him to obviate the difficulty of understanding

how the sun can work its way underground from west to east during the

night. Actual observation must also have suggested to him his central

doctrine, that Fire is the one permanent substance, of which all

visible things are passing phases. In combustion we see things change

utterly, while their flame and heat rise up into the air and vanish.

"This world, which is the same for all," he says, "no one of gods or

men has made; but it was ever, is now, and ever shall be, an

ever-living Fire, with measures kindling, and measures going out."

"The transformations of Fire are, first of all, sea; and half of the

sea is earth, half whirlwind."

This theory, though no longer one which science can accept, is

nevertheless scientific in spirit. Science, too, might have inspired

the famous saying to which Plato alludes: "You cannot step twice into

the same rivers; for fresh waters are ever flowing in upon you." But

we find also another statement among the extant fragments: "We step

and do not step into the same rivers; we are and are not."

The comparison of this statement, which is mystical, with the one

quoted by Plato, which is scientific, shows how intimately the two

tendencies are blended in the system of Heraclitus.

Mysticism is, in

essence, little more than a certain intensity and depth of feeling in

regard to what is believed about the universe; and this kind of

feeling leads Heraclitus, on the basis of his science, to strangely

poignant sayings concerning life and the world, such as:

"Time is a child playing draughts, the kingly power is a child's."

It is poetic imagination, not science, which presents Time as despotic

lord of the world, with all the irresponsible frivolity of a child. It

is mysticism, too, which leads Heraclitus to assert the identity of

opposites: "Good and ill are one," he says; and again:

"To God all

things are fair and good and right, but men hold some things wrong and

some right."

Much of mysticism underlies the ethics of Heraclitus. It is true that

a scientific determinism alone might have inspired the statement:

"Man's character is his fate"; but only a mystic would have said:

"Every beast is driven to the pasture with blows"; and again:

"It is hard to fight with one's heart's desire. Whatever it wishes to

get, it purchases at the cost of soul"; and again:

"Wisdom is one thing. It is to know the thought by which all things

are steered through all things."[1]

Examples might be multiplied, but those that have been given are

enough to show the character of the man: the facts of science, as they

appeared to him, fed the flame in his soul, and in its light he saw

into the depths of the world by the reflection of his own dancing

swiftly penetrating fire. In such a nature we see the true union of

the mystic and the man of science--the highest eminence, as I think,

that it is possible to achieve in the world of thought.

In Plato, the same twofold impulse exists, though the mystic impulse

is distinctly the stronger of the two, and secures ultimate victory

whenever the conflict is sharp. His description of the cave is the

classical statement of belief in a knowledge and reality truer and

more real than that of the senses:

"Imagine[2] a number of men living in an underground cavernous

chamber, with an entrance open to the light, extending along the

entire length of the cavern, in which they have been confined, from

their childhood, with their legs and necks so shackled that they

are obliged to sit still and look straight forwards, because their

chains render it impossible for them to turn their heads round: and

imagine a bright fire burning some way off, above and behind them,

and an elevated roadway passing between the fire and the prisoners,

with a low wall built along it, like the screens which conjurors

put up in front of their audience, and above which they exhibit

their wonders.

I have it, he replied.

Also figure to yourself a number of persons walking behind this

wall, and carrying with them statues of men, and images of other

animals, wrought in wood and stone and all kinds of materials,

together with various other articles, which overtop the wall; and,

as you might expect, let some of the passers-by be talking, and

others silent.

You are describing a strange scene, and strange prisoners.

They resemble us, I replied.

Now consider what would happen if the course of nature brought them

a release from their fetters, and a remedy for their foolishness,

in the following manner. Let us suppose that one of them has been

released, and compelled suddenly to stand up, and turn his neck

round and walk with open eyes towards the light; and let us suppose

that he goes through all these actions with pain, and that the

dazzling splendour renders him incapable of discerning those

objects of which he used formerly to see the shadows.

What answer

should you expect him to make, if some one were to tell him that in

those days he was watching foolish phantoms, but that now he is

somewhat nearer to reality, and is turned towards things more real,

and sees more correctly; above all, if he were to point out to him

the several objects that are passing by, and question him, and

compel him to answer what they are? Should you not expect him to be

puzzled, and to regard his old visions as truer than the objects

now forced upon his notice?

Yes, much truer....

Hence, I suppose, habit will be necessary to enable him to perceive

objects in that upper world. At first he will be most successful in

distinguishing shadows; then he will discern the reflections of men

and other things in water, and afterwards the realities; and after

this he will raise his eyes to encounter the light of the moon and

stars, finding it less difficult to study the heavenly bodies and

the heaven itself by night, than the sun and the sun's light by

day.

Doubtless.

Last of all, I imagine, he will be able to observe and contemplate

the nature of the sun, not as it _appears_ in water or on alien

ground, but as it is in itself in its own territory.

Of course.

His next step will be to draw the conclusion, that the sun is the

author of the seasons and the years, and the guardian of all things

in the visible world, and in a manner the cause of all those things

which he and his companions used to see.

Obviously, this will be his next step....

Now this imaginary case, my dear Glancon, you must apply in all its

parts to our former statements, by comparing the region which the

eye reveals to the prison house, and the light of the fire therein

to the power of the sun: and if, by the upward ascent and the

contemplation of the upper world, you understand the mounting of

the soul into the intellectual region, you will hit the tendency of

my own surmises, since you desire to be told what they are; though,

indeed, God only knows whether they are correct. But, be that as it

may, the view which I take of the subject is to the following

effect. In the world of knowledge, the essential Form of Good is

the limit of our enquiries, and can barely be perceived; but, when

perceived, we cannot help concluding that it is in every case the

source of all that is bright and beautiful,--in the visible world

giving birth to light and its master, and in the intellectual world

dispensing, immediately and with full authority, truth and

reason;--and that whosoever would act wisely, either in private or

in public, must set this Form of Good before his eyes."

But in this passage, as throughout most of Plato's teaching, there is

an identification of the good with the truly real, which became

embodied in the philosophical tradition, and is still largely

operative in our own day. In thus allowing a legislative function to

the good, Plato produced a divorce between philosophy and science,

from which, in my opinion, both have suffered ever since and are still

suffering. The man of science, whatever his hopes may be, must lay

them aside while he studies nature; and the philosopher, if he is to

achieve truth, must do the same. Ethical considerations can only

legitimately appear when the truth has been ascertained: they can and

should appear as determining our feeling towards the truth, and our

manner of ordering our lives in view of the truth, but not as

themselves dictating what the truth is to be.

There are passages in Plato--among those which illustrate the

scientific side of his mind--where he seems clearly aware of this. The

most noteworthy is the one in which Socrates, as a young man, is

explaining the theory of ideas to Parmenides.

After Socrates has explained that there is an idea of the good, but

not of such things as hair and mud and dirt, Parmenides advises him

"not to despise even the meanest things," and this advice shows the

genuine scientific temper. It is with this impartial temper that the

mystic's apparent insight into a higher reality and a hidden good has

to be combined if philosophy is to realise its greatest possibilities.

And it is failure in this respect that has made so much of idealistic

philosophy thin, lifeless, and insubstantial. It is only in marriage

with the world that our ideals can bear fruit: divorced from it, they

remain barren. But marriage with the world is not to be achieved by an

ideal which shrinks from fact, or demands in advance that the world

shall conform to its desires.

Parmenides himself is the source of a peculiarly interesting strain

of mysticism which pervades Plato's thought--the mysticism which may

be called "logical" because it is embodied in theories on logic. This

form of mysticism, which appears, so far as the West is concerned, to

have originated with Parmenides, dominates the reasonings of all the

great mystical metaphysicians from his day to that of Hegel and his

modern disciples. Reality, he says, is uncreated, indestructible,

unchanging, indivisible; it is "immovable in the bonds of mighty

chains, without beginning and without end; since coming into being and

passing away have been driven afar, and true belief has cast them

away." The fundamental principle of his inquiry is stated in a

sentence which would not be out of place in Hegel: "Thou canst not

know what is not--that is impossible--nor utter it; for it is the same

thing that can be thought and that can be." And again:

"It needs must

be that what can be thought and spoken of is; for it is possible for

it to be, and it is not possible for what is nothing to be." The

impossibility of change follows from this principle; for what is past

can be spoken of, and therefore, by the principle, still is.

Mystical philosophy, in all ages and in all parts of the world, is

characterised by certain beliefs which are illustrated by the

doctrines we have been considering.

There is, first, the belief in insight as against discursive analytic

knowledge: the belief in a way of wisdom, sudden, penetrating,

coercive, which is contrasted with the slow and fallible study of

outward appearance by a science relying wholly upon the senses. All

who are capable of absorption in an inward passion must have

experienced at times the strange feeling of unreality in common

objects, the loss of contact with daily things, in which the solidity

of the outer world is lost, and the soul seems, in utter loneliness,

to bring forth, out of its own depths, the mad dance of fantastic

phantoms which have hitherto appeared as independently real and

living. This is the negative side of the mystic's initiation: the

doubt concerning common knowledge, preparing the way for the reception

of what seems a higher wisdom. Many men to whom this negative

experience is familiar do not pass beyond it, but for the mystic it is

merely the gateway to an ampler world.

The mystic insight begins with the sense of a mystery unveiled, of a

hidden wisdom now suddenly become certain beyond the possibility of a

doubt. The sense of certainty and revelation comes earlier than any

definite belief. The definite beliefs at which mystics arrive are the

result of reflection upon the inarticulate experience gained in the

moment of insight. Often, beliefs which have no real connection with

this moment become subsequently attracted into the central nucleus;

thus in addition to the convictions which all mystics share, we find,

in many of them, other convictions of a more local and temporary

character, which no doubt become amalgamated with what was essentially

mystical in virtue of their subjective certainty. We may ignore such

inessential accretions, and confine ourselves to the beliefs which all

mystics share.

The first and most direct outcome of the moment of illumination is

belief in the possibility of a way of knowledge which may be called

revelation or insight or intuition, as contrasted with sense, reason,

and analysis, which are regarded as blind guides leading to the morass

of illusion. Closely connected with this belief is the conception of a

Reality behind the world of appearance and utterly different from it.

This Reality is regarded with an admiration often amounting to

worship; it is felt to be always and everywhere close at hand, thinly

veiled by the shows of sense, ready, for the receptive mind, to shine

in its glory even through the apparent folly and wickedness of Man.

The poet, the artist, and the lover are seekers after that glory: the

haunting beauty that they pursue is the faint reflection of its sun.

But the mystic lives in the full light of the vision: what others

dimly seek he knows, with a knowledge beside which all other knowledge

is ignorance.

The second characteristic of mysticism is its belief in unity, and its

refusal to admit opposition or division anywhere. We found Heraclitus

saying "good and ill are one"; and again he says, "the way up and the

way down is one and the same." The same attitude appears in the

simultaneous assertion of contradictory propositions, such as: "We

step and do not step into the same rivers; we are and are not." The

assertion of Parmenides, that reality is one and indivisible, comes

from the same impulse towards unity. In Plato, this impulse is less

prominent, being held in check by his theory of ideas; but it

reappears, so far as his logic permits, in the doctrine of the primacy

of the Good.

A third mark of almost all mystical metaphysics is the denial of the

reality of Time. This is an outcome of the denial of division; if all

is one, the distinction of past and future must be illusory. We have

seen this doctrine prominent in Parmenides; and among moderns it is

fundamental in the systems of Spinoza and Hegel.

The last of the doctrines of mysticism which we have to consider is

its belief that all evil is mere appearance, an illusion produced by

the divisions and oppositions of the analytic intellect.

Mysticism

does not maintain that such things as cruelty, for example, are good,

but it denies that they are real: they belong to that lower world of

phantoms from which we are to be liberated by the insight of the

vision. Sometimes--for example in Hegel, and at least verbally in

Spinoza--not only evil, but good also, is regarded as illusory, though

nevertheless the emotional attitude towards what is held to be Reality

is such as would naturally be associated with the belief that Reality

is good. What is, in all cases, ethically characteristic of mysticism

is absence of indignation or protest, acceptance with joy, disbelief

in the ultimate truth of the division into two hostile camps, the good

and the bad. This attitude is a direct outcome of the nature of the

mystical experience: with its sense of unity is associated a feeling

of infinite peace. Indeed it may be suspected that the feeling of

peace produces, as feelings do in dreams, the whole system of

associated beliefs which make up the body of mystic doctrine. But this

is a difficult question, and one on which it cannot be hoped that

mankind will reach agreement.

Four questions thus arise in considering the truth or falsehood of

mysticism, namely:

I. Are there two ways of knowing, which may be called respectively

reason and intuition? And if so, is either to be preferred to the

other?

II. Is all plurality and division illusory?

III. Is time unreal?

IV. What kind of reality belongs to good and evil?

On all four of these questions, while fully developed mysticism seems

to me mistaken, I yet believe that, by sufficient restraint, there is

an element of wisdom to be learned from the mystical way of feeling,

which does not seem to be attainable in any other manner. If this is

the truth, mysticism is to be commended as an attitude towards life,

not as a creed about the world. The meta-physical creed, I shall

maintain, is a mistaken outcome of the emotion, although this emotion,

as colouring and informing all other thoughts and feelings, is the

inspirer of whatever is best in Man. Even the cautious and patient

investigation of truth by science, which seems the very antithesis of

the mystic's swift certainty, may be fostered and nourished by that

very spirit of reverence in which mysticism lives and moves.

I. REASON AND INTUITION[3]

Of the reality or unreality of the mystic's world I know nothing. I

have no wish to deny it, nor even to declare that the insight which

reveals it is not a genuine insight. What I do wish to maintain--and

it is here that the scientific attitude becomes imperative--is that

insight, untested and unsupported, is an insufficient guarantee of

truth, in spite of the fact that much of the most important truth is

first suggested by its means. It is common to speak of an opposition

between instinct and reason; in the eighteenth century, the opposition

was drawn in favour of reason, but under the influence of Rousseau and

the romantic movement instinct was given the preference, first by

those who rebelled against artificial forms of government and thought,

and then, as the purely rationalistic defence of traditional theology

became increasingly difficult, by all who felt in science a menace to

creeds which they associated with a spiritual outlook on life and the

world. Bergson, under the name of "intuition," has raised instinct to

the position of sole arbiter of metaphysical truth. But in fact the

opposition of instinct and reason is mainly illusory.

Instinct,

intuition, or insight is what first leads to the beliefs which

subsequent reason confirms or confutes; but the confirmation, where it

is possible, consists, in the last analysis, of agreement with other

beliefs no less instinctive. Reason is a harmonising, controlling

force rather than a creative one. Even in the most purely logical

realm, it is insight that first arrives at what is new.

Where instinct and reason do sometimes conflict is in regard to single

beliefs, held instinctively, and held with such determination that no

degree of inconsistency with other beliefs leads to their abandonment.

Instinct, like all human faculties, is liable to error.

Those in whom

reason is weak are often unwilling to admit this as regards

themselves, though all admit it in regard to others.

Where instinct is

least liable to error is in practical matters as to which right

judgment is a help to survival: fr