History of Modern Philosophy From Nicolas of Cusa to the Present Time by Richard Falckenberg - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

to God; _i.e._, they possess religion. In man, natural and animal religion

are completed by rational religion, the limitations of which render a

revelation necessary. A religion can be considered divine only when it is

adapted to all, when it gains acceptance through miracles and virtue, and

when it contradicts neither natural ethics nor the reason. Religion is

union with God through knowledge, purity of will, and love. It is inborn,

a law of nature, not, as Machiavelli teaches, a political invention.

Campanella desired to see the unity in the divine government of the world

embodied in a pyramid of states with the papacy at the apex: above the

individual states was to come the province, then the kingdom, the empire,

the (Spanish) world-monarchy, and, finally, the universal dominion of the

Pope. The Church should be superior to the State, the vicegerent of God to

temporal rulers and to councils.

%4. Philosophy of the State and of Law%.

The originality of the modern doctrines of natural law was formerly

overestimated, as it was not known to how considerable an extent the way

had been prepared for them by the mediaeval philosophy of the state and of

law. It is evident from the equally rich and careful investigations of Otto

Gierke[1] that in the political and legal theories of a Bodin, a Grotius,

a Hobbes, a Rousseau, we have systematic developments of principles long

extant, rather than new principles produced with entire spontaneity. Their

merit consists in the principiant expression and accentuation and the

systematic development of ideas which the Middle Ages had produced, and

which in part belong to the common stock of Scholastic science, in part

constitute the weapons of attack for bold innovators.

Marsilius of Padua

(_Defensor Pacis_, 1325), Occam (died 1347), Gerson (about 1400), and the

Cusan[2] _(Concordantia Catholica_, 1433) especially, are now seen in a

different light. "Under the husk of the mediaeval system there is revealed

a continuously growing antique-modern kernel, which draws all the living

constituents out of the husk, and finally bursts it"

(Gierke, _Deutsches

Genossenschaftsrecht_, vol. iii. p. 312). Without going beyond the

boundaries of the theocratico-organic view of the state prevalent in

the Middle Ages, most of the conceptions whose full development was

accomplished by the natural law of modern times were already employed in

the Scholastic period. Here we already find the idea of a transition on the

part of man from a pre-political natural state of freedom and equality into

the state of citizenship; the idea of the origin of the state by a contract

(social and of submission); of the sovereignty of the ruler (_rex major

populo; plenitudo potestatis_), and of popular sovereignty[3] (_populus

major principe_); of the original and inalienable prerogatives of the

generality, and the innate and indestructible right of the individual to

freedom; the thought that the sovereign power is superior to positive

law _(princeps legibus solutus_), but subordinate to natural law; even

tendencies toward the division of powers (legislative and executive),

and the representative system. These are germs which, at the fall of

Scholasticism and the ecclesiastical reformation, gain light and air for

free development.

[Footnote 1: Gierke, _Johannes Althusius und die Entwickelung der

naturrechtlichen Staatstheorien_, Breslau, 1880; the same, _Deutsches

Genossenschaftsrecht_, vol. iii. § II, Berlin, 1881. Cf.

further, Sigm.

Riezler, _Die literarischen Widersacher der Päpste_, Leipsic, 1874; A.

Franck, _Réformateurs et Publicistes de L'Europe_, Paris, 1864.]

[Footnote 2: Nicolas' political ideas are discussed by T. Stumpf, Cologne,

1865.]

[Footnote 3: Cf. F. von Bezold, _Die Lehre von der Volkssouveränität im

Mittelalter_, (Sybel's _Historische Zeitschrift_, vol.

xxxvi., 1876).]

The modern theory of natural law, of which Grotius was the most influential

representative, began with Bodin and Althusius. The former conceives

the contract by which the state is founded as an act of unconditional

submission on the part of the community to the ruler, the latter conceives

it merely as the issue of a (revocable) commission: in the view of the one,

the sovereignty of the people is entirely alienated,

"transferred," in that

of the other, administrative authority alone is granted,

"conceded," while

the sovereign prerogatives remain with the people. Bodin is the founder

of the theory of absolutism, to which Grotius and the school of Pufendorf

adhere, though in a more moderate form, and which Hobbes develops to the

last extreme. Althusius, on the other hand, by his systematic development

of the doctrine of social contract and the inalienable sovereignty of the

people, became the forerunner of Locke[1] and Rousseau.

[Footnote 1: Ulrich Huber (1674) may be called the first representative

of constitutionalism, and so the intermediate link between Althusius and

Locke. Cf. Gierke, _Althusius_, p. 290.]

The first independent political philosopher of the modern period was

Nicolo Machiavelli of Florence (1469-1527). Patriotism was the soul of his

thinking, questions of practical politics its subject, and historical fact

its basis.[1] He is entirely unscholastic and unecclesiastical. The power

and independence of the nation are for him of supreme importance, and the

greatness and unity of Italy, the goal of his political system. He

opposes the Church, the ecclesiastical state, and the papacy as the chief

hindrances to the attainment of these ends, and considers the means by

which help may be given to the Fatherland. In normal circumstances a

republican constitution, under which Sparta, Rome, and Venice have achieved

greatness, would be the best. But amid the corruption of the times, the

only hope of deliverance is from the absolute rule of a strong prince,

one not to be frightened back from severity and force.

Should the ruler

endeavor to keep within the bounds of morality, he would inevitably be

ruined amid the general wickedness. Let him make himself liked, especially

make himself feared, by the people; let him be fox and lion together; let

him take care, when he must have recourse to bad means for the sake of the

Fatherland, that they are justified by the result, and still to preserve

the appearance of loyalty and honor when he is forced to act in their

despite--for the populace always judges by appearance and by results. The

worst thing of all is half-way measures, courses intermediate between good

and evil and vacillating between reason and force. Even Moses had to kill

the envious refractories, while Savonarola, the unarmed prophet, was

destroyed. God is the friend of the strong, energy the chief virtue; and

it is well when, as was the case with the ancient Romans, religion is

associated with it without paralyzing it. The current view of Christianity

as a religion of humility and sloth, which preaches only the courage

of endurance and makes its followers indifferent to worldly honor,

is unfavorable to the development of political vigor.

The Italians have

been made irreligious by the Church and the priesthood; the nearer Rome,

the less pious the people. When Machiavelli, in his proposals looking

toward Lorenzo (II.) dei Medici (died 1519), approves any means for

restoring order, it must be remembered that he has an exceptional case

in mind, that he does not consider deceit and severity just, but only

unavoidable amid the anarchy and corruption of the time.

But neither the

loftiness of the end by which he is inspired, nor the low condition of

moral views in his time, justifies his treatment of the laws as mere means

to political ends, and his unscrupulous subordination of morality to

calculating prudence. Machiavelli's general view of the world and of life

is by no means a comforting one. Men are simple, governed by their passions

and by insatiable desires, dissatisfied with what they have, and inclined

to evil. They do good only of necessity; it is hunger which makes them

industrious and laws that render them good. Everything rapidly degenerates:

power produces quiet, quiet, idleness, then disorder, and, finally, ruin,

until men learn by misfortune, and so order and power again arise. History

is a continual rising and falling, a circle of order and disorder.

Governmental forms, even, enjoy no stability; monarchy, when it has run out

into tyranny, is followed by aristocracy, which gradually passes over into

oligarchy; this in turn is replaced by democracy, until, finally, anarchy

becomes unendurable, and a prince again attains power.

No state, however,

is so powerful as to escape succumbing to a rival before it completes the

circuit. Protection against the corruption of the state is possible only

through the maintenance of its principles, and its restoration only by a

return to the healthy source whence it originated. This is secured either

by some external peril compelling to reflection, or internally, by wise

thought, by good laws (framed in accordance with the general welfare, and

not according to the ambition of a minority), and by the example of good

men.

[Footnote 1: In his _Essays on the First Decade of Livy (Discorsi)_,

Machiavelli investigates the conditions and the laws of the maintenance of

states; while in _The Prince (II Principe_, 1515), he gives the principles

for the restoration of a ruined state. Besides these he wrote a history

of Florence, and a work on the art of war, in which he recommended the

establishment of national armies.]

In the interval between Machiavelli and the system of natural law of

Grotius, the Netherlander (1625: _De Jure Belli et Pacis_), belong the

socialistic ideal state of the Englishman, Thomas More (_De Optimo

Reipublicae Statu deque Nova Insula Utopia_, 1516), the political theory of

the Frenchman, Jean Bodin (_Six Livres de la République_, 1577, Latin 1584;

also a philosophico-historical treatise, _Methodus ad Facilem Historiarum

Cognitionem_, and the _Colloquium Heptaplomeres_, edited by Noack, 1857),

and the law of war of the Italian, Albericus Gentilis, at his death

professor in Oxford (_De Jure Belli_, 1588). Common to these three was

the advocacy of religious tolerance, from which atheists alone were to

be excepted; common, also, their ethical standpoint in opposition to

Machiavelli, while they are at one with him in regard to the liberation of

political and legal science from theology and the Church. With Gentilis

(1551-1611) this separation assigns the first five commandments to divine,

and the remainder to human law, the latter being based on the laws of human

nature (especially the social impulse). In place of this derivation of law

and the state from the nature of man, Jean Bodin (1530-96) insists on an

historical interpretation; endeavors, though not always with success, to

give sharp definitions of political concepts;[1] rejects composite

state forms, and among the three pure forms, monarchy, aristocracy, and

democracy, rates (hereditary) monarchy the highest, in which the subjects

obey the laws of the monarch, and the latter the laws of God or of nature

by respecting the freedom and the property of the citizens. So far, no

one has correctly distinguished between forms of the state and modes of

administration. Even a democratic state may be governed in a monarchical

or aristocratic way. So far, also, there has been a failure to take into

account national peculiarities and differences of situation, conditions to

which legislation must be adjusted. The people of the temperate zone are

inferior to those of the North in physical power and inferior to those of

the South in speculative ability, but superior to both in political gifts

and in the sense of justice. The nations of the North are guided by

force, those of the South by religion, those between the two by reason.

Mountaineers love freedom. A fruitful soil enervates men, when less

fertile, it renders them temperate and industrious.

[Footnote 1: What is the state? What is sovereignty? The former is defined

as the rational and supremely empowered control over a number of families

and of whatever is common to them; the latter is absolute and continuous

authority over the state, with the right of imposing laws without being

bound by them. The prince, to whom the sovereignty has been unconditionally

relinquished by the people in the contract of submission, is accountable to

God alone.]

Attention has only recently been called (by O. Gierke, in the work already

mentioned, Heft vii. of his _Untersuchungen zur deutschen Staats- und

Rechtsgeschichte_, Breslau, 1880) to the Westphalian, Johannes Althusius

(Althusen or Althaus) as a legal philosopher worthy of notice. He was born,

1557, in the Grafschaft Witgenstein; was a teacher of law in Herborn and

Siegen from 1586, and Syndic in Emden from 1604 to his death in 1638. His

chief legal work was the _Dicaeologica_, 1617 (a recasting of a treatise

on Roman law which appeared in 1586), and his chief political work the

_Politica_, 1603 (altered and enlarged 1610, and reprinted, in addition,

three times before his death and thrice subsequently).

Down to the

beginning of the eighteenth century he was esteemed or opposed as chief

among the _Monarchomachi_, so called by the Scotchman, Barclay (_De Regno

et Regali Potestate_, 1600); since that time he has fallen into undeserved

oblivion. The sovereign power (_majestas_) of the people is untransferable

and indivisible, the authority vested in the chosen wielder of the

administrative power is revocable, and the king is merely the chief

functionary; individuals are subjects, it is true, but the community

retains its sovereignty and has its rights represented over against the

chief magistrate by a college of ephors. If the prince violates the

compact, the ephors are authorized and bound to depose the tyrant, and to

banish or execute him. There is but one normal state-form; monarchy and

polyarchy are mere differences in administrative forms.

Mention should

finally be made of his valuation of the social groups which mediate between

the individual and the state: the body politic is based on the narrower

associations of the family, the corporation, the commune, and the province.

While with Bodin the historical, and with Gentilis the _a priori_ method of

treatment predominates, Hugo Grotius[1] combines both standpoints. He bases

his system on the traditional distinction of two kinds of law. The origin

of positive law is historical, by voluntary enactment; natural law is

rooted in the nature of man, is eternal, unchangeable, and everywhere the

same. He begins by distinguishing with Gentilis the _jus humanum_ from the

_jus divinum_ given in the Scriptures. The former determines, on the one

hand, the legal relations of individuals, and, on the other, those of whole

nations; it is _jus personale_ and _jus gentium_.[2]

[Footnote 1: Hugo de Groot lived 1583-1645. He was born in Delft, became

Fiscal of Holland in 1607, and Syndic of Rotterdam and member of the States

General in 1613. A leader of the aristocratic party with Oldenbarneveld, he

adhered to the Arminians or Remonstrants, was thrown into prison, freed in

1621 through the address of his wife, and fled to Paris, where he lived

till 1631 as a private scholar, and, from 1635, as Swedish ambassador. Here

he composed his epoch-making work, _De Jure Belli et Pacis_, 1625. Previous

to this had appeared his treatise, _De Veritate Religionis Christianae_,

1619, and the _Mare Liberum_, 1609, the latter a chapter from his maiden

work, _De Jure Praedae_, which was not printed until 1868.]

[Footnote 2: The meaning which Grotius here gives to _jus gentium_

(=international law), departs from the customary usage of the Scholastics,

with whom it denotes the law uniformly acknowledged among all nations.

Thomas Aquinas understands by it, in distinction to _jus naturale_ proper,

the sum of the conclusions deduced from this as a result of the development

of human culture and its departure from primitive purity. Cf. Gierke,

_Althusius_, p. 273; _Deutsches Genossenschaftsrecht_, vol. iii. p. 612.

On the meaning of natural law cf. Gierke's Inaugural Address as Rector at

Breslau, _Naturrecht und Deutsches Recht_, Frankfort-on-the-Main, 1883.]

The distinction between natural and conventional law which has been already

mentioned, finds place within both: the positive law of persons is called

_jus civile_, and the positive law of nations, _jus gentium voluntarium_.

Positive law has its origin in regard for utility, while unwritten law

finds its source neither in this nor (directly) in the will of God,[1] but

in the rational nature of man. Man is by nature social, and, as a rational

being, possesses the impulse toward ordered association.

Unlawful means

whatever renders such association of rational beings impossible, as the

violation of promises or the taking away and retention of the property

of others. In the (pre-social) state of nature, all belonged to all, but

through the act of taking possession _(occupatio)_

property arises (sea and

air are excluded from appropriation). In the state of nature everyone has

the right to defend himself against attack and to revenge himself on the

evil-doer; but in the political community, founded by contract, personal

revenge is replaced by punishment decreed by the civil power. The aim of

punishment is not retribution, but reformation and deterrence. It belongs

to God alone to punish because of sin committed, the state can punish only

to prevent it. (The antithesis _quia peccatum est_--_ne peccetur_ comes

from Seneca.)

[Footnote 1: Natural law would be valid even if there were no God. With

these words the alliance between the modern and the mediaeval philosophy of

law is severed.]

This energetic revival of the distinction already common in the Middle Ages

between "positive and natural," which Lord Herbert of Cherbury brought

forward at the same period (1624) in the philosophy of religion, gave the

catchword for a movement in practical philosophy whose developments extend

into the nineteenth century. Not only the illumination period, but all

modern philosophy down to Kant and Fichte, is under the ban of the

antithesis, natural and artificial. In all fields, in ethics as well as in

noëtics, men return to the primitive or storm back to it, in the hope of

finding there the source of all truth and the cure for all evils. Sometimes

it is called nature, sometimes reason (natural law and rational law are

synonymous, as also natural religion and the religion of the reason), by

which is understood that which is permanent and everywhere the same in

contrast to the temporary and the changeable, that which is innate in

contrast to that which has been developed, in contrast, further, to that

which has been revealed. Whatever passes as law in all places and at all

times is natural law, says Grotius; that which all men believe forms the

content of natural religion, says Lord Herbert. Before long it comes to

be said: that _alone_ is genuine, true, healthy, and valuable which has

eternal and universal validity; all else is not only superfluous and

valueless but of evil, for it must be unnatural and corrupt. This step is

taken by Deism, with the principle that whatever is not natural or rational

in the sense indicated is unnatural and irrational.

Parallel phenomena are

not wanting, further, in the philosophy of law (Gierke, _Althusius_). But

these errors must not be too harshly judged. The confidence with which they

were made sprang from the real and the historical force of their underlying

idea.

As already stated, the "natural" forms the antithesis to the supernatural,

on the one hand, and to the historical, on the other.

This combination of

the revealed and the historical will not appear strange, if we remember

that the mediaeval view of the world under criticism was, as Christian,

historico-religious, and, moreover, that for the philosophy of religion the

two in fact coincide, inasmuch as revelation is conceived as an historical

event, and the historical religions assume the character of revealed. The

term arbitrary, applied to both in common, was questionable, however: as

revelation is a divine decree, so historical institutions are the products

of human enactment, the state, the result of a contract, dogmas, inventions

of the priesthood, _the results of development, artificial constructions_!

It took long ages for man to free himself from the idea of the artificial

and conventional in his view of history. Hegel was the first to gather

the fruit whose seeds had been sown by Leibnitz, Lessing, Herder, and the

historical school of law. As often, however, as an attempt was made from

this standpoint of origins to show laws in the course of history, only one

could be reached, a law of necessary degeneration, interrupted at times

by sudden restorations--thus the Deists, thus Machiavelli and Rousseau.

Everything degenerates, science itself only contributes to the

fall--therefore, back to the happy beginnings of things!

If, finally, we inquire into the position of the Church in regard to the

questions of legal philosophy, we may say that, among the Protestants,

Luther, appealing to the Scripture text, declares rulers ordained by God

and sacred, though at the same time he considers law and politics but

remotely related to the inner man; that Melancthon, in his _Elements of

Ethics_ (1538), as in all his philosophical text-books,[1] went back to

Aristotle, but found the source of natural law in the Decalogue, being

followed in this by Oldendorp (1539), Hemming (1562), and B. Winkler

(1615).[2]

[Footnote 1: The edition of Melancthon's works by Bretschneider and

Bindseil gives the ethical treatises in vol. xvi. and the other

philosophical treatises in vol. xiii. (in part also in vols. xi. and xx.).]

[Footnote 2: Cf. C.v. Kaltenborn, _Die Vorläufer des Hugo Grotius_,

Leipsic, 1848.]

On the Catholic side, the Jesuits (the Order was founded in 1534, and

confirmed in 1540), on the one hand, revived the Pelagian theory of freedom

in opposition to the Luthero-Augustinian doctrine of the servitude of the

will, and, on the other, defended the natural origin of the state in a

(revocable) contract in opposition to its divine origin asserted by the

Reformers, and the sovereignty of the people even to the sanctioning of

tyrannicide. Bellarmin (1542-1621) taught that the prince derives his

authority from the people, and as the latter have given him power, so they

retain the natural right to take it back and bestow it elsewhere. The view

of Juan Mariana (1537-1624; _De Rege_, 1599) is that, as the people in

transferring rights to the prince retain still greater power themselves,

they are entitled in given cases to call the king to account. If he

corrupts the state by evil manners, and, degenerating into the tyrant,

despises religion and the laws, he may, as a public enemy, be deprived by

anyone of his authority and his life. It is lawful to arrest tyranny in any

way, and those have always been highly esteemed who, from devotion to the

public welfare, have sought to kill the tyrant.

%5. Skepticism in France.%

Toward the end of the sixteenth century, and in the very country which was