An Essay Concerning Humane Understanding by John Locke - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

APPROACH OF TWO BODIES, WHEN THEY ARE MOVED ONE TOWARDS ANOTHER, I

CALL

SOLIDITY. I wil not dispute whether this acceptation of the word solid

be nearer to its original signification than that which mathematicians

use it in. It suffices that I think the common notion of solidity will

al ow, if not justify, this use of it; but if any one think it better to

call it IMPENETRABILITY, he has my consent. Only I have thought the term

solidity the more proper to express this idea, not only because of its

vulgar use in that sense, but also because it carries something more of

positive in it than impenetrability; which is negative, and is perhaps

more a consequence of solidity, than solidity itself. This, of all

other, seems the idea most intimately connected with, and essential to

body; so as nowhere else to be found or imagined, but only in matter.

And though our senses take no notice of it, but in masses of matter, of

a bulk sufficient to cause a sensation in us: yet the mind, having once

got this idea from such grosser sensible bodies, traces it further, and

considers it, as well as figure, in the minutest particle of matter

that can exist; and finds it inseparably inherent in body, wherever or

however modified.

2. Solidity fils Space.

This is the idea which belongs to body, whereby we conceive it to fil

space. The idea of which filling of space is,--that where we imagine any

space taken up by a solid substance, we conceive it so to possess it,

that it excludes al other solid substances; and wil for ever hinder

any other two bodies, that move towards one another in a straight line,

from coming to touch one another, unless it removes from between them

in a line not parallel to that which they move in. This idea of it,

the bodies which we ordinarily handle sufficiently furnish us with.

3. Distinct from Space.

This resistance, whereby it keeps other bodies out of the space which it

possesses, is so great, that no force, how great soever, can surmount

it. All the bodies in the world, pressing a drop of water on all sides,

will never be able to overcome the resistance which it wil make, soft

as it is, to their approaching one another, til it be removed out of

their way: whereby our idea of solidity is distinguished both from pure

space, which is capable neither of resistance nor motion; and from

the ordinary idea of hardness. For a man may conceive two bodies at

a distance, so as they may approach one another, without touching

or displacing any solid thing, till their superficies come to meet;

whereby, I think, we have the clear idea of space without solidity. For

(not to go so far as annihilation of any particular body) I ask, whether

a man cannot have the idea of the motion of one single body alone,

without any other succeeding immediately into its place? I think it is

evident he can: the idea of motion in one body no more including the

idea of motion in another, than the idea of a square figure in one body

includes the idea of a square figure in another. I do not ask, whether

bodies do so EXIST, that the motion of one body cannot really be without

the motion of another. To determine this either way, is to beg the

question for or against a VACUUM. But my question is,--whether one

cannot have the IDEA of one body moved, whilst others are at rest? And I

think this no one will deny. If so, then the place it deserted gives us

the idea of pure space without solidity; whereinto any other body may

enter, without either resistance or protrusion of anything. When the

sucker in a pump is drawn, the space it fil ed in the tube is certainly

the same whether any other body follows the motion of the sucker or not:

nor does it imply a contradiction that, upon the motion of one body,

another that is only contiguous to it should not follow it. The

necessity of such a motion is built only on the supposition that the

world is full; but not on the distinct IDEAS of space and solidity,

which are as different as resistance and not resistance, protrusion and

not protrusion. And that men have ideas of space without a body, their

very disputes about a vacuum plainly demonstrate, as is shown in another

place.

4. From Hardness.

Solidity is hereby also differenced from hardness, in that solidity

consists in repletion, and so an utter exclusion of other bodies out of

the space it possesses: but hardness, in a firm cohesion of the parts of

matter, making up masses of a sensible bulk, so that the whole does not

easily change its figure. And indeed, hard and soft are names that we

give to things only in relation to the constitutions of our own bodies;

that being generally called hard by us, which wil put us to pain sooner

than change figure by the pressure of any part of our bodies; and that,

on the contrary, soft, which changes the situation of its parts upon an

easy and unpainful touch.

But this difficulty of changing the situation of the sensible parts

amongst themselves, or of the figure of the whole, gives no more

solidity to the hardest body in the world than to the softest; nor is an

adamant one jot more solid than water. For, though the two flat sides of

two pieces of marble will more easily approach each other, between which

there is nothing but water or air, than if there be a diamond between

them; yet it is not that the parts of the diamond are more solid than

those of water, or resist more; but because the parts of water, being

more easily separable from each other, they will, by a side motion, be

more easily removed, and give way to the approach of the two pieces of

marble. But if they could be kept from making place by that side motion,

they would eternally hinder the approach of these two pieces of marble,

as much as the diamond; and it would be as impossible by any force to

surmount their resistance, as to surmount the resistance of the parts of

a diamond. The softest body in the world will as invincibly resist the

coming together of any other two bodies, if it be not put out of the

way, but remain between them, as the hardest that can be found or

imagined. He that shall fill a yielding soft body well with air or

water, wil quickly find its resistance. And he that thinks that nothing

but bodies that are hard can keep his hands from approaching one

another, may be pleased to make a trial, with the air inclosed in a

football. The experiment, I have been told, was made at Florence, with

a hollow globe of gold filled with water, and exactly closed; which

further shows the solidity of so soft a body as water. For the golden

globe thus filled, being put into a press, which was driven by the

extreme force of screws, the water made itself way through the pores of

that very close metal, and finding no room for a nearer approach of its

particles within, got to the outside, where it rose like a dew, and so

fell in drops, before the sides of the globe could be made to yield to

the violent compression of the engine that squeezed it.

5. On Solidity depend Impulse, Resistance and Protrusion.

By this idea of solidity is the extension of body distinguished from

the extension of space:--the extension of body being nothing but the

cohesion or continuity of solid, separable, movable parts; and the

extension of space, the continuity of unsolid, inseparable, and

immovable parts. Upon the solidity of bodies also depend their mutual

impulse, resistance, and protrusion. Of pure space then, and solidity,

there are several (amongst which I confess myself one) who persuade

themselves they have clear and distinct ideas; and that they can think

on space, without anything in it that resists or is protruded by body.

This is the idea of pure space, which they think they have as clear

as any idea they can have of the extension of body: the idea of the

distance between the opposite parts of a concave superficies being

equally as clear without as with the idea of any solid parts between:

and on the other side, they persuade themselves that they have, distinct

from that of pure space, the idea of SOMETHING THAT FILLS SPACE, that

can be protruded by the impulse of other bodies, or resist their motion.

If there be others that have not these two ideas distinct, but confound

them, and make but one of them, I know not how men, who have the same

idea under different names, or different ideas under the same name, can

in that case talk with one another; any more than a man who, not being

blind or deaf, has distinct ideas of the colour of scarlet and the sound

of a trumpet, could discourse concerning scarlet colour with the blind

man I mentioned in another place, who fancied that the idea of scarlet

was like the sound of a trumpet.

6. What Solidity is.

If any one asks me, WHAT THIS SOLIDITY IS, I send him to his senses to

inform him. Let him put a flint or a football between his hands, and

then endeavour to join them, and he will know. If he thinks this not a

sufficient explication of solidity, what it is, and wherein it consists;

I promise to tell him what it is, and wherein it consists, when he tells

me what thinking is, or wherein it consists; or explains to me what

extension or motion is, which perhaps seems much easier. The simple

ideas we have, are such as experience teaches them us; but if, beyond

that, we endeavour by words to make them clearer in the mind, we shall

succeed no better than if we went about to clear up the darkness of a

blind man's mind by talking; and to discourse into him the ideas of

light and colours. The reason of this I shall show in another place.

CHAPTER V.

OF SIMPLE IDEAS OF DIVERS SENSES.

Ideas received both by seeing and touching.

The ideas we get by more than one sense are, of SPACE or EXTENSION,

FIGURE, REST, and MOTION. For these make perceivable impressions, both

on the eyes and touch; and we can receive and convey into our minds the

ideas of the extension, figure, motion, and rest of bodies, both by

seeing and feeling. But having occasion to speak more at large of these

in another place, I here only enumerate them.

CHAPTER VI.

OF SIMPLE IDEAS OF REFLECTION.

Simple Ideas are the Operations of Mind about its other Ideas.

The mind receiving the ideas mentioned in the foregoing chapters from

without, when it turns its view inward upon itself, and observes its own

actions about those ideas it has, takes from thence other ideas, which

are as capable to be the objects of its contemplation as any of those it

received from foreign things.

The Idea of Perception, and Idea of Willing, we have from Reflection.

The two great and principal actions of the mind, which are most

frequently considered, and which are so frequent that every one that

pleases may take notice of them in himself, are these two:--

PERCEPTION, or THINKING; and VOLITION, or WILLING.

The power of thinking is caled the UNDERSTANDING, and the power of

volition is cal ed the WILL; and these two powers or abilities in the

mind are denominated faculties.

Of some of the MODES of these simple ideas of reflection, such as are

REMEMBRANCE, DISCERNING, REASONING, JUDGING, KNOWLEDGE, FAITH, &c., I

shall have occasion to speak hereafter.

CHAPTER VII.

OF SIMPLE IDEAS OF BOTH SENSATION AND REFLECTION.

1. Ideas of Pleasure and Pain.

There be other simple ideas which convey themselves into the mind by all

the ways of sensation and reflection, viz. PLEASURE or DELIGHT, and its

opposite, PAIN, or UNEASINESS; POWER; EXISTENCE; UNITY mix with almost

al our other Ideas.

2. Delight or uneasiness, one or other of them, join themselves to

almost all our ideas both of sensation and reflection: and there is

scarce any affection of our senses from without, any retired thought of

our mind within, which is not able to produce in us pleasure or pain. By

pleasure and pain, I would be understood to signify, whatsoever delights

or molests us; whether it arises from the thoughts of our minds, or

anything operating on our bodies. For, whether we call it; satisfaction,

delight, pleasure, happiness, &c., on the one side, I or uneasiness,

trouble, pain, torment, anguish, misery, &c., the other, they are still

but different degrees of the same thing, and belong to the ideas of

pleasure and pain, delight or uneasiness; which are the names I shall

most commonly use for those two sorts of ideas.

3. As motives of our actions.

The infinite wise Author of our being, having given us the power over

several parts of our bodies, to move or keep them at rest as we think

fit; and also, by the motion of them, to move ourselves and other

contiguous bodies, in which consist all the actions of our body: having

also given a power to our minds, in several instances, to choose,

amongst its ideas, which it will think on, and to pursue the inquiry of

this or that subject with consideration and attention, to excite us to

these actions of thinking and motion that we are capable of,--has been

pleased to join to several thoughts, and several sensations a perception

of delight. If this were whol y separated from al our outward

sensations, and inward thoughts, we should have no reason to prefer one

thought or action to another; negligence to attention, or motion to

rest. And so we should neither stir our bodies, nor employ our minds,

but let our thoughts (if I may so call it) run adrift, without any

direction or design, and suffer the ideas of our minds, like unregarded

shadows, to make their appearances there, as it happened, without

attending to them. In which state man, however furnished with the

faculties of understanding and will, would be a very idle, inactive

creature, and pass his time only in a lazy, lethargic dream. It has

therefore pleased our wise Creator to annex to several objects, and the

ideas which we receive from them, as also to several of our thoughts, a

concomitant pleasure, and that in several objects, to several degrees,

that those faculties which he had endowed us with might not remain

wholly idle and unemployed by us.

4. An end and use of pain.

Pain has the same efficacy and use to set us on work that pleasure has,

we being as ready to employ our faculties to avoid that, as to pursue

this: only this is worth our consideration, that pain is often produced

by the same objects and ideas that produce pleasure in us. This their

near conjunction, which makes us often feel pain in the sensations where

we expected pleasure, gives us new occasion of admiring the wisdom and

goodness of our Maker, who, designing the preservation of our being, has

annexed pain to the application of many things to our bodies, to warn us

of the harm that they wil do, and as advices to withdraw from them. But

he, not designing our preservation barely, but the preservation of every

part and organ in its perfection, hath in many cases annexed pain to

those very ideas which delight us. Thus heat, that is very agreeable to

us in one degree, by a little greater increase of it proves no ordinary

torment: and the most pleasant of al sensible objects, light itself,

if there be too much of it, if increased beyond a due proportion to our

eyes, causes a very painful sensation. Which is wisely and favourably so

ordered by nature, that when any object does, by the vehemency of its

operation, disorder the instruments of sensation, whose structures

cannot but be very nice and delicate, we might, by the pain, be warned

to withdraw, before the organ be quite put out of order, and so be

unfitted for its proper function for the future. The consideration of

those objects that produce it may wel persuade us, that this is the end

or use of pain. For, though great light be insufferable to our eyes, yet

the highest degree of darkness does not at all disease them: because

that, causing no disorderly motion in it, leaves that curious organ

unarmed in its natural state. But yet excess of cold as wel as heat

pains us: because it is equally destructive to that temper which is

necessary to the preservation of life, and the exercise of the several

functions of the body, and which consists in a moderate degree of

warmth; or, if you please, a motion of the insensible parts of our

bodies, confined within certain bounds.

5. Another end.

Beyond all this, we may find another reason why God hath scattered up

and down several degrees of pleasure and pain, in al the things that

environ and affect us; and blended them together in almost al that our

thoughts and senses have to do with;--that we, finding imperfection,

dissatisfaction, and want of complete happiness, in all the enjoyments

which the creatures can afford us, might be led to seek it in the

enjoyment of Him with whom there is fullness of joy, and at whose right

hand are pleasures for evermore.

6. Goodness of God in annexing pleasure and pain to our other ideas.

Though what I have here said may not, perhaps, make the ideas of

pleasure and pain clearer to us than our own experience does, which is

the only way that we are capable of having them; yet the consideration

of the reason why they are annexed to so many other ideas, serving to

give us due sentiments of the wisdom and goodness of the Sovereign

Disposer of all things, may not be unsuitable to the main end of these

inquiries: the knowledge and veneration of him being the chief end of

al our thoughts, and the proper business of all understandings.

7. Ideas of Existence and Unity.

EXISTENCE and UNITY are two other ideas that are suggested to the

understanding by every object without, and every idea within. When ideas

are in our minds, we consider them as being actually there, as wel

as we consider things to be actually without us;--which is, that they

exist, or have existence. And whatever we can consider as one thing,

whether a real being or idea, suggests to the understanding the idea of

unity.

8. Idea of Power.

POWER also is another of those simple ideas which we receive from

sensation and reflection. For, observing in ourselves that we do and

can think, and that we can at pleasure move several parts of our bodies

which were at rest; the effects, also, that natural bodies are able to

produce in one another, occurring every moment to our senses,--we both

these ways get the idea of power.

9. Idea of Succession.

Besides these there is another idea, which, though suggested by our

senses, yet is more constantly offered to us by what passes in our

minds; and that is the idea of SUCCESSION. For if we look immediately

into ourselves, and reflect on what is observable there, we shall find

our ideas always, whilst we are awake, or have any thought, passing in

train, one going and another coming, without intermission.

10. Simple Ideas the materials of al our Knowledge.

These, if they are not all, are at least (as I think) the most

considerable of those simple ideas which the mind has, out of which is

made all its other knowledge; al which it receives only by the two

forementioned ways of sensation and reflection.

Nor let any one think these too narrow bounds for the capacious mind of

man to expatiate in, which takes its flight further than the stars, and

cannot be confined by the limits of the world; that extends its thoughts

often even beyond the utmost expansion of Matter, and makes excursions

into that incomprehensible Inane. I grant al this, but desire any one

to assign any SIMPLE IDEA which is not received from one of those inlets

before mentioned, or any COMPLEX IDEA not made out of those simple ones.

Nor wil it be so strange to think these few simple ideas sufficient to

employ the quickest thought, or largest capacity; and to furnish the

materials of all that various knowledge, and more various fancies and

opinions of al mankind, if we consider how many words may be made out

of the various composition of twenty-four letters; or if, going one step

further, we wil but reflect on the variety of combinations that may be

made with barely one of the above-mentioned ideas, viz. number, whose

stock is inexhaustible and truly infinite: and what a large and immense

field doth extension alone afford the mathematicians?

CHAPTER VIII.

SOME FURTHER CONSIDERATIONS CONCERNING OUR SIMPLE IDEAS OF

SENSATION.

1. Positive Ideas from privative causes.

Concerning the simple ideas of Sensation; it is to be considered,--that

whatsoever is so constituted in nature as to be able, by affecting our

senses, to cause any perception in the mind, doth thereby produce in the

understanding a simple idea; which, whatever be the external cause of

it, when it comes to be taken notice of by our discerning faculty, it is

by the mind looked on and considered there to be a real positive idea in

the understanding, as much as any other whatsoever; though, perhaps, the

cause of it be but a privation of the subject.

2. Ideas in the mind distinguished from that in things which gives rise

to them.

Thus the ideas of heat and cold, light and darkness, white and black,

motion and rest, are equally clear and positive ideas in the mind;

though, perhaps, some of the causes which produce them are barely

privations, in those subjects from whence our senses derive those ideas.

These the understanding, in its view of them, considers all as distinct

positive ideas, without taking notice of the causes that produce

them: which is an inquiry not belonging to the idea, as it is in the

understanding, but to the nature of the things existing without us.

These are two very different things, and carefully to be distinguished;

it being one thing to perceive and know the idea of white or black, and

quite another to examine what kind of particles they must be, and how

ranged in the superficies, to make any object appear white or black.

3. We may have the ideas when we are ignorant of their physical causes.

A painter or dyer who never inquired into their causes hath the ideas

of white and black, and other colours, as clearly, perfectly, and

distinctly in his understanding, and perhaps more distinctly, than the

philosopher who hath busied himself in considering their natures, and

thinks he knows how far either of them is, in its cause, positive or

privative; and the idea of black is no less positive in his mind than

that of white, however the cause of that colour in the external object

may be only a privation.

4. Why a privative cause in nature may occasion a positive idea.

If it were the design of my present undertaking to inquire into the

natural causes and manner of perception, I should offer this as a reason

why a privative cause might, in some cases at least, produce a positive

idea; viz. that all sensation being produced in us only by different

degrees and modes of motion in our animal spirits, variously agitated by

external objects, the abatement of any former motion must as necessarily

produce a new sensation as the variation or increase of it; and so

introduce a new idea, which depends only on a different motion of the

animal spirits in that organ.

5. Negative names need not be meaningless.

But whether this be so or not I wil not here determine, but appeal

to every one's own experience, whether the shadow of a man, though it

consists of nothing but the absence of light (and the more the absence

of light is, the more discernible is the shadow) does not, when a man

looks on it, cause as clear and positive idea in his mind, as a man

himself, though covered over with clear sunshine? And the picture of a

shadow is a positive thing. Indeed, we have negative names, to which

there be no positive ideas; but they consist wholly in negation of some

certain ideas, as SILENCE, INVISIBLE; but these signify not any ideas in

the mind but their absence.

6. Whether any ideas are due to causes really private.

And thus one may truly be said to see dark