Sextus Empiricus and Greek scepticism by Mary Mills Patrick - HTML preview

PLEASE NOTE: This is an HTML preview only and some elements such as links or page numbers may be incorrect.
Download the book in PDF, ePub, Kindle for a complete version.

animals have of the same objects are demonstrated by their

different tastes, as the things desired by some are fatal to

others.[2] The practical illustrations given of this result show

a familiarity with natural history, and cognizance of the tastes

and habits of many animals,[3] but were probably few of them

original with Sextus, unless perhaps in their application; that

this train of reasoning was the common property of the Sceptic

School, we know from the fact that Diogenes begins his exposition of the first Trope in a way similar to that of

Sextus.[4] His illustrations are, however, few and meagre

compared with those of Sextus, and the scientific facts used by

both of them may mostly be found in other authors of antiquity

given in a similar way.[5] The logical result of the reasoning

used to explain the first Trope, is that we cannot compare the

ideas of the animals with each other, nor with our own; nor can

we prove that our ideas are more trustworthy than those of the

animals.[6] As therefore an examination of ideas is impossible,

any decided opinion about their trustworthiness is also impossible, and this Trope leads to the suspension of judgment

regarding external objects, or to [Greek: epochê.][7]

[1] _Hyp._. I. 54.

[2] _Hyp._. I. 55.

[3] _Hyp._. I. 55-59.

[4] Diog. IX. 11, 79-80.

[5] Pappenheim _Erlauterung Pyrr. Grundzüge Par_.

41.

[6] _Hyp_. I. 59.

[7] _Hyp_. I. 61.

After reaching this conclusion, Sextus introduces a long chapter

to prove that animals can reason. There is no reference to this

in Diogenes, but there is other testimony to show that it was a

favourite line of argument with the Sceptics.[1] Sextus, however, says that his course of reasoning is different from

that of most of the Sceptics on the subject,[2] as they usually

applied their arguments to all animals, while he selected only

one, namely the dog.[3] This chapter is full of sarcastic

attacks on the Dogmatics, and contains the special allusion to

the Stoics as the greatest opponents of the Sceptics, which has

been before referred to.[4]

Sextus claims with a greater freedom of diction than in some

apparently less original chapters, and with a wealth of special

illustrations, that the dog is superior to man in acuteness of

perception,[5] that he has the power of choice, and possesses an

art, that of hunting,[6] and, also, is not deprived of virtue,[7] as the true nature of virtue is to show justice to

all, which the dog does by guarding loyally those who are kind

to him, and keeping off those who do evil.[8] The reasoning

power of this animal is proved by the story taken from Chrysippus, of the dog that came to a meeting of three roads in

following a scent. After seeking the scent in vain in two of the

roads, he takes the third road without scenting it as a result

of a quick process of thought, which proves that he shares in

the famous dialectic of Chrysippus,[9] the five forms of

[Greek:

_anapodeiktoi logoi_,] of which the dog chooses the fifth.

Either _A_ or _B_ or _C_, not _A_ or _B,_ therefore _C_.

[1] _Hyp_. I. 238.

[2] Compare Brochard _Op. cit._ 256.

[3] _Hyp_. I. 62-63.

[4] _Hyp_. I. 65.

[5] _Hyp_. I. 64.

[6] _Hyp_. I. 66.

[7] _Hyp_. I. 67.

[8] _Hyp_. I. 67.

[9] _Hyp_. I. 69; _Hyp_. II. 166; Diog. VII. 1, 79.

The dog and other irrational animals may also possess spoken

language, as the only proof that we have to the contrary, is the

fact that we cannot understand the sounds that they make.[1] We

have an example in this chapter of the humor of Sextus, who

after enlarging on the perfect character of the dog, remarks,

"For which reason it seems to me some philosophers have honoured

themselves with the name of this animal,"[2] thus making a

sarcastic allusion to the Cynics, especially Antisthenes.[3]

[1] _Hyp_. I. 74.

[2] _Hyp_. I. 72.

[3] Diog. VI. 1, 13.

_The Second Trope_. Passing on to the second Trope, Sextus aims

to prove that even if we leave the differences of the mental

images of animals out of the discussion, there is not a sufficient unanimity in the mental images of human beings to

allow us to base any assertions upon them in regard to the

character of external objects.[1] He had previously announced

that he intended to oppose the phenomenal to the intellectual

"in any way whatever,"[2] so he begins here by referring to the

two parts of which man is said to be composed, the soul and the

body, and proceeds to discuss the differences among men in

sense-perception and in opinion.[3] Most of the illustrations

given of differences in sense-perception are medical ones; of

the more general of these I will note the only two which are

also given by Diogenes in his exposition of this Trope,[4] viz.,

Demophon, Alexander's table waiter, who shivered in the sun, and

Andron the Argive, who was so free from thirst that he travelled

through the desert of Libya without seeking a drink.

Some have

reasoned from the presence of the first of these illustrations

in the exposition of the Tropes, that a part of this material at

least goes back to the time of Pyrrho, as Pyrrho from his

intimacy with Alexander, when he accompanied him to India, had

abundant opportunities to observe the peculiarities of his

servant Demophon.[5] The illustration of Andron the Argive is

taken from Aristotle, according to Diogenes.[6]

[1] _Hyp_. I. 79.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 8.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 80.

[4] Diog. IX. 11, 80-81.

[5] Compare _Pyrrhon et le Scepticism primitive, Revue

phil._, Paris 1885, No. 5; Victor Brochard, p.

521.

[6] Diog. IX. 11, 81.

Passing on to differences of opinion, we have another example of

the sarcastic humor of Sextus, as he refers to the

[Greek:

physiognômonikê sophia][1] as the authority for believing that

the body is a type of the soul. As the bodies of men differ, so

the souls also probably differ. The differences of mind among

men is not referred to by Diogenes, except in the general

statement that they choose different professions; while Sextus

elaborates this point, speaking of the great differences in

opposing schools of philosophy, and in the objects of choice and

avoidance, and sources of pleasure for different men.[2]

The

poets well understand this marked difference in human desires,

as Homer says,

"One man enjoys this, another enjoys that."

Sextus also quotes the beautiful lines of Pindar,[3]

"One delights in getting honours and crowns through

stormfooted horses,

Others in passing life in rooms rich in gold, Another safe travelling enjoys, in a swift ship, on a wave of the sea."

[1] _Hyp._ I. 85.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 87-89.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 86.

_The Third Trope_. The third Trope limits the argument to the

sense-perceptions of one man, a Dogmatic, if preferred, or to

one whom the Dogmatics consider wise,[1] and states that as the

ideas given by the different sense organs differ radically in a

way that does not admit of their being compared with each other,

they furnish no reliable testimony regarding the nature of

objects.[2] "Each of the phenomena perceived by us seems to

present itself in many forms, as the apple, smooth, fragrant

brown and sweet." The apple was evidently the ordinary example

given for this Trope, for Diogenes uses the same, but in a much

more condensed form, and not with equal understanding of the

results to be deduced from it.[3] The consequence of the incompatibility of the mental representations produced through

the several sense organs by the apple, may be the acceptance of

either of the three following propositions: (i) That only those

qualities exist in the apple which we perceive. (ii) That more

than these exist. (iii) That even those perceived do not exist.[4] Accordingly, any experience which can give rise to

such different views regarding outward objects, cannot be relied

upon as a testimony concerning them.

[1] _Hyp._ I. 90.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 94.

[3] Diog. IX. 11 81.

[4] _Hyp._ I. 99.

The non-homogeneous nature of the mental images connected with

the different sense organs, as presented by Sextus, reminds us

of the discussion of the same subject by Berkeley in his _Theory

of Vision_.

Sextus says that a man born with less than the usual number of

senses, would form altogether different ideas of the external

world than those who have the usual number, and as our ideas of

objects depend on our mental images, a greater number of sense

organs would give us still different ideas of outward reality.[1] The strong argument of the Stoics against such

reasoning as this, was their doctrine of pre-established harmony

between nature and the soul, so that when a representation is

produced in us of a real object, a [Greek: katalêptikê phantasia],[2] by this representation the soul grasps a real

existence. There is a [Greek: logos] in us which is of the same

kind, [Greek: syngenos], or in relation to all nature.

This

argument of pre-established harmony between the faculties of the

soul and the objects of nature, is the one that has been used in

all ages to combat philosophical teaching that denies that we

apprehend the external world as it is. It was used against Kant

by his opponents, who thought in this way to refute his teachings.[3] The Sceptics could not, of course, accept a theory

of nature that included the soul and the external world in one

harmonious whole, but Sextus in his discussion of the third

Trope does not refute this argument as fully as he does later in

his work against logic.[4] He simply states here that philosophers themselves cannot agree as to what nature is, and

furthermore, that a philosopher himself is a part of the discord, and to be judged, rather than being capable of judging,

and that no conclusion can be reached by those who are themselves an element of the uncertainty.[5]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 96-97.

[2] _Adv. Math._ VII. 93.

[3] Ueberweg _Op. cit._ 195.

[4] _Adv. Math._ VII. 354.

[5] _Hyp._ I. 98-99.

_The Fourth Trope_. This Trope limits the argument to each

separate sense, and the effect is considered of the condition of

body and mind upon sense-perception in relation to the several

sense-organs.[1] The physical states which modify sense-perception are health and illness, sleeping and waking,

youth and age, hunger and satiety, drunkenness and sobriety. All

of these conditions of the body entirely change the character of

the mental images, producing different judgments of the color,

taste, and temperature of objects, and of the character of

sounds. A man who is asleep is in a different world from one

awake, the existence of both worlds being relative to the

condition of waking and sleeping.[2]

The subjective states which Sextus mentions here as modifying

the character of the mental representations are hating or

loving, courage or fear, sorrow or joy, and sanity or insanity.[3] No man is ever twice in exactly the same condition

of body or mind, and never able to review the differences of his

ideas as a sum total, for those of the present moment only are

subject to careful inspection.[4] Furthermore, no one is free

from the influence of all conditions of body or mind, so that he

can be unbiassed to judge his ideas, and no criterion can be

established that can be shown to be true, but on the contrary,

whatever course is pursued on the subject, both the criterion

and the proof will be thrown into the _circulus in probando_,

for the truth of each rests on the other.[5]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 100.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 104.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 100.

[4] _Hyp._ I. 112.

[5] _Hyp._ I. 117.

Diogenes gives in part the same illustrations of this Trope, but

in a much more condensed form. The marked characteristic of this

train of reasoning is the attempt to prove that abnormal conditions are also natural. In referring at first to the

opposing states of body and mind, which so change the character

of sense-perception, Sextus classifies them according to the

popular usage as [Greek: kata physin] and [Greek: para physin].

This distinction was an important one, even with Aristotle, and

was especially developed by the Stoics[1] in a broader sense

than referring merely to health and sickness. The Stoics,

however, considered only normal conditions as being according to

nature. Sextus, on the contrary, declares that abnormal states

are also conditions according to nature,[2] and just as those

who are in health are in a state that is natural to those who

are in health, so also those not in health are in a state that

is natural to those not in health, and in some respects according to nature. Existence, then, and non-existence are not

absolute, but relative, and the world of sleep as really exists

for those who are asleep as the things that exist in waking

exist, although they do not exist in sleep.[3] One mental

representation, therefore, cannot be judged by another, which is

also in a state of relation to existing physical and mental

conditions. Diogenes states this principle even more decidedly

in his exposition of this Trope. "The insane are not in a

condition opposed to nature; why they more than we? For we also

see the sun as if it were stationary."[4] Furthermore, in

different periods of life ideas differ. Children are fond of

balls and hoops, while those in their prime prefer other things,

and the aged still others.[5] The wisdom contained in this Trope

in reference to the relative value of the things most sought

after is not original with Sextus, but is found in the more

earnest ethical teachings of older writers. Sextus does not,

however, draw any moral conclusions from this reasoning, but

only uses it as an argument for [Greek: epochê].

[1] Diog. VII. 1, 86.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 103.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 104.

[4] Diog. IX. 11, 82.

[5] _Hyp._ I. 106.

_The Fifth Trope_. This Trope leaves the discussion of the

dependence of the ideas upon the physical nature, and takes up

the influence of the environment upon them. It makes the difference in ideas depend upon the position, distance, and

place of objects, thus taking apparently their real existence

for granted. Things change their form and shape according to the

distance from which they are observed, and the position in which

they stand.[1]

The same light or tone alters decidedly in different surroundings. Perspective in paintings depends on the angle at

which the picture is suspended.[2] With Diogenes this Trope is

the seventh,[3] and his exposition of it is similar, but as

usual, shorter. Both Sextus and Diogenes give the illustration[4] of the neck of the dove differing in color in

different degrees of inclination, an illustration used by

Protagoras also to prove the relativity of perception by the

senses. "The black neck of the dove in the shade appears black,

but in the light sunny and purple."[5] Since, then, all phenomena are regarded in a certain place, and from a certain

distance, and according to a certain position, each of which

relations makes a great difference with the mental images, we

shall be obliged also by this Trope to come to the reserving of

the opinion.[6]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 118.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 120.

[3] Diog. IX. 11, 85.

[4] _Hyp._ I. 120; Diog. IX. 11, 86.

[5] _Schol. zu Arist._ 60, 18, ed. Brandis; Pappen.

_Er.

Pyrr. Grundzüge_, p. 54.

[6] _Hyp._ I. 121.

_The Sixth Trope_. This Trope leads to [Greek: epochê]

regarding

the nature of objects, because no object can ever be presented

to the organs of sense directly, but must always be perceived

through some medium, or in some mixture.[1] This mixture may be

an outward one, connected with the temperature, or the rarity of

the air, or the water[2] surrounding an object, or it may be a

mixture resulting from the different humors of the sense-organs.[3] A man with the jaundice, for example, sees

colors differently from one who is in health. The illustration

of the jaundice is a favorite one with the Sceptics.

Diogenes

uses it several times in his presentation of Scepticism, and it

occurs in Sextus' writings in all, as an illustration, in eight

different places.[4] The condition of the organ of the

[Greek:

hêgemonikon], or the ruling faculty, may also cause mixtures.

Pappenheim thinks that we have here Kant's idea of _a priori_,

only on a materialistic foundation.[5] A careful consideration

of the passage, however, shows us that Sextus' thought is more

in harmony with the discoveries of modern psychiatry than with

the philosophy of Kant. If the sentence, [Greek: isôs de kai

autê (hê dianoia) epimixian tina idian poieitai pros ta hypo tôn

aisthêseôn anangellomena],[6] stood alone, without further

explanation, it might well refer to _a priori_ laws of thought,

but the explanation which follows beginning with

"because" makes

that impossible.[7] "Because in each of the places where the

Dogmatics think that the ruling faculty is, we see present

certain humors, which are the cause of mixtures." Sextus does

not advance any opinion as to the place of the ruling faculty in

the body, which is, according to the Stoics, the principal part

of the soul, where ideas, desires, and reasoning originate,[8]

but simply refers to the two theories of the Dogmatics, which

claim on the one hand that it is in the brain, and on the other

that it is in the heart.[9] This subject he deals with more

fully in his work against logic.[10] As, however, he bases his

argument, in discussing possible intellectual mixtures in

illustration of the sixth Trope, entirely on the condition of

the organ of the intellect, it is evident that his theory of the

soul was a materialistic one.

[1] _Hyp._ I. 124.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 125.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 126.

[4] See Index to Bekker's edition of Sextus.

[5] Papp. _Er. Pyr. Gr._ p. 55.

[6] _Hyp._ I. 128.

[7] _Hyp._ I. 128.

[8] Diog. VII. 1, 159.

[9] _Hyp._ I. 128.

[10] _Adv. Math._ VII. 313.

_The Seventh Trope_. This Trope, based upon the quantities and

compositions of objects, is illustrated by examples of different

kinds of food, drink, and medicine, showing the different

effects according to the quantity taken, as the harmfulness and

the usefulness of most things depend on their quantity.

Things

act differently upon the senses if applied in small or large

quantities, as filings of metal or horn, and separate grains of

sand have a different color and touch from the same taken in the

form of a solid.[1] The result is that ideas vary according to

the composition of the object, and this Trope also brings to

confusion the existence of outward objects, and leads us to

reserve our opinion in regard to them.[2] This Trope is illustrated by Diogenes with exceeding brevity.[3]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 129-131.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 134.

[3] Diog. IX. 11, 86.

_The Eighth Trope_. The Trope based upon relation contains, as

Sextus rightly remarks, the substance of the other nine,[1] for

the general statement of the relativity of knowledge includes

the other statements made. The prominence which Sextus gave this

Trope in his introduction to the ten Tropes leads one to expect

here new illustrations and added[2] arguments for

[Greek:

epochê]. We find, however, neither of these, but simply a

statement that all things are in relation in one of two ways,

either directly, or as being a part of a difference.

These two

kinds of relation are given by Protagoras, and might have been

used to good purpose in the introduction to the Tropes, or at

the end, to prove that all the others were really subordinate to

the eighth. The reasoning is, however simply applied to the

relation of objects to each other, and nothing is added that is

not found elsewhere where as an argument for [Greek: epochê].[3]

This Trope is the tenth by Diogenes, and he strengthens his

reasoning in regard to it, by a statement that Sextus does not

directly make, _i.e._, that everything is in relation to the

understanding.[4]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 39.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 135-140.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 135-140.

[4] Diog. IX. 11, 88.

_The Ninth Trope_. This is based upon the frequency and rarity

of events, and refers to some of the phenomena of nature, such

as the rising of the sun, and the sea, as no longer a source of

astonishment, while a comet or an earthquake are wonders to

those not accustomed to them.[1] The value of objects also

depends on their rarity, as for example the value of gold.[2]

Furthermore, things may be valuable at one time, and at another

not so, according to the frequency and rarity of the occurrence.[3] Therefore this Trope also leads to

[Greek:

epochê]. Diogenes gives only two illustrations to this Trope,

that of the sun and the earthquake.[4]

[1] _Hyp._ I. 141-142.

[2] _Hyp._ I. 143.

[3] _Hyp._ I. 144.

[4] Diog. IX. 11, 87.

_The Tenth Trope_. We have already remarked on the difference in

the character of the tenth Trope, dealing as it does, not with

the ideas of objects, like the other nine Tropes, but with

philosophical and religious